Home Economics
|
|
|||||
The Return to FormThe role of form in Aquinas’s ontology is to determine structure. Structure, in turn, determines the organization of reality. This is what Aquinas calls a formal cause. As Haldane noted: ‘If realism is to be vindicated, the relevant relationship between the content of a veridical state and its object is one of identity.’[1] It is through an analysis of form that ontological realism and epistemological realism hold together. Aquinas means more by ‘form’ and ‘formal cause’ than the mere arrangement of physical structure of an entity of a natural kind. Substantial form is ‘determinative’ of the essential or sortal properties of a kind. Following Aristotle, the form of a biological kind determines a complex integrated set of metabolic processes concerned with sustaining life, growth, sensation in animals, mobility, and so forth. In the case of non-living primary substances, the function of the form is what ultimately counts for tensile strength, ductility, whether or not it is a good conductor of electricity, and so forth. An individual of a natural kind will have a form-dependent physical arrangement; much more than this, however, arrangement is form-dependent and essential to a specific kind of primary substance. Regarding substantial form, ontological realism argues that there exists a structured world independent of consciousness. The correlative to ontological realism is epistemological realism, which claims that in perception and thought, a human knower is capable of direct awareness of the world and of attaining knowledge of its structure. In the metaphysics and philosophy of mind of Aquinas, both ontological realism and epistemological realism depend on an analysis of form, both substantial forms for sortal properties and accidental forms for incidental characteristics. Representationalism or representative realism is the theoretical rival of epistemological realism, which illustrates the wide gap between Aquinas and Descartes. What does the analysis put forward in this chapter entail? The following ten propositions follow from the extended discussion developed above:
It follows that isomorphism of structure or form is a necessary condition for understanding intentionality theory in Aquinas. The two Latin propositions ‘Sensus in actu est sensible in actu and ‘Intellectus in actu est intelligible in actu denote this isomorphism. The explication of these two propositions is: (a) the sense faculty in perceiving (in actu) is the identical form of the extensional sensible object (in actu); and (b) the possible intellect (intellectuspossibilis in actu) in knowing a set of sortal properties (the essence) is, in principle, identical with the natural kind (in actu) in the external world. The ‘est’ is the ‘is of identity’. In conclusion, what Aquinas contributes to the contemporary discussion in the philosophy of mind might be articulated in the following set of propositions:
The analysis put forward in this study is rooted in Aquinas’s Commentary on Aristotle’s On the Soul. In the end, this chapter is in agreement with Haldane’s suggestion: ‘in their own ways influential figures such as McDowell and Putnam have been working towards positions very close to that of Aristotle and Aquinas.’48 In a different context, Kenny wrote: ‘I believe as a matter of fact, that the clearest insight into the nature of the mind is to be obtained from the Aristotelian viewpoint.’[2] If this analysis is correct, this explains the subtitle for this chapter: ‘From Aquinas to Brentano and Beyond’, which suggests that this analysis of intentionality theory rooted in Brentano is of more than merely historical interest. Possibly the insights of medieval philosophy may assist philosophers to go beyond Brentano and his successors in the philosophy of mind. 48 Ibid., 42. |
<< | CONTENTS | >> |
---|
Related topics |